79 pages • 2 hours read
A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more. For select classroom titles, we also provide Teaching Guides with discussion and quiz questions to prompt student engagement.
Wollstonecraft uses this chapter to describe the various factors that “degrade the sex” (57) and thereby make it almost impossible for women to acquire the understanding and reasoning that would enable them to be dependent of men. The degradation she describes here refers to the fact that most women consider it their sole purpose to please, a point Wollstonecraft supports by quoting from a poem by a popular contemporary female poet—Mrs. [Anna Letitia] Barbauld. The final line of the poem reads: “Nor blush, my fair, to own you copy these; Your BEST, your SWEETEST empire is to PLEASE.” (57).
Part of the reason it’s so difficult for women to practice reason and intelligence, Wollstonecraft says, is because of the way in which they are treated by men. According to Wollstonecraft, men believe that woman was created merely to be “his solace” (56). She continues to describe how a man will treat a woman—even one of profound intelligence and learning—differently from how he would treat another man, affording her only “hollow respect” (59) and treating her like “a queen” (59) by closing doors for her and holding her handkerchief. It’s these marks of “hollow respect” (59) that Wollstonecraft believes only degrade women further, perpetuating the misconception of them as frail, weak beings who must be looked after and cared for by a man, and who are unable to perform even basic tasks themselves.
There are other factors that perpetuate the misconception of women as frail beings. Wollstonecraft says that it’s only natural for mankind to crave admiration and respect, and to want to raise their position in life. However, women do not have the same ability as men to rise in their station and, to do so, their only option is to “marry advantageously” (63). Similarly, to gain respect and admiration, women often exaggerate their so-called feminine traits—such as beauty, frailty, and softness of mind—as the quickest and surest way to gain the attention of men: “When do we hear of women who, starting out of obscurity, boldly claim respect on account of their great abilities or daring virtues?” (61). As a result, Wollstonecraft says that women instead become “slaves” (65) to their senses “because it is by their sensibility that they obtain present power” (65). Wollstonecraft argues that women should be educated like men so that they might have power over themselves.
Many of Wollstonecraft’s contemporaries—including male writers—argue that while men were born to think, women were born to feel, and that, together, they make a perfect whole. Wollstonecraft pushes back against this argument by stating that sensibility is not in the image of God, while reason is. Furthermore, even if women are going to stay inside the home to perform domestic duties, sensibility or emotion alone will not help them perform these tasks:
Yet women, whose minds are not enlarged by cultivation, or the natural selfishness of sensibility expanded by reflection, are very unfit to manage a family; for, by an undue stretch of power, they are always tyrannizing to support a superiority that only rests on the arbitrary distinction of fortune (70).
Here, Wollstonecraft turns her argument towards marriage. She suggests that if women are only raised to practice sensibility and to endeavor to please, then all marriages will rest purely on the passions, rather than mutual esteem. Instead, Wollstonecraft says that “when even two virtuous young people marry, it would […] perhaps be happy if some circumstances checked their passion” (77), as passion fades rapidly and, if there is nothing else that holds two people together, then both will turn elsewhere for affection. Instead, if women were educated, they would seek out a marriage of fairness and equality, rather than one that would elevate their rank and that relies purely on passion and superficial attraction.
In this chapter, Wollstonecraft consecutively examines and critiques a number of contemporary writers and their views regarding female character and education. The chapter is made up of five sections that focus, in turn, on a specific writer or group of writers.
Rousseau and his writings are the focus of Section 1. In particular, Wollstonecraft discusses Rousseau’s work Emile, or On Education, a text that documents the upbringing and education of Emile and his fiancée, Sophie. Wollstonecraft quotes extensively from Rousseau’s writing in order to illustrate his belief that the sole purpose of woman is to “please, to be useful to us, to make us love and esteem them, to educate us when young, and take care of us when grown up” (84).
Rousseau states that the differences between the sexes is visible from an early age, where “boys love sports of noise and activity” (84), while girls “are fonder of things of show and ornament” (85). Wollstonecraft argues that such differences are not instinctive and fundamental, but simply “the effect of habit” (85). For years, girls and women have been raised and educated to be interested in such “feminine” interests. Furthermore, Rousseau also asserts “a state of dependence [upon men] being natural to [women]” (87), an argument Wollstonecraft firmly pushes back against by asking, “Considering the length of time that women have been dependent, is it surprising that some of them hug their chains, and fawn like the spaniel?” (87).
Rousseau believes that women do have certain advantages over men—such as their beauty and “ingenuity” (89)—which creates a system of mutual dependency, and so women should ensure to develop and cherish such advantages. However, Wollstonecraft attacks the fundamental basis of such an idea, stating that men and women should not aspire for dependency but rather should seek independence from one another, an equality which would allow them to enter into a mutual partnership. Similarly, although Rousseau encourages women to refine their feminine attributes, he simultaneously encourages women to “keep [their husbands] at some distance from your person” (94) in order to “maintain the authority in love” (94). In contradiction, Wollstonecraft states that such an education—one that encourages vanity and teasing—will not make “chaste wives and sensible mothers” (94) and instead encourages the opposite:
Will it be allowed that the surest way to make a wife chaste is to teach her to practice the wanton arts of a mistress, termed virtuous coquetry, by the sensualist who can no longer relish the artless charms of sincerity, or taste the pleasure arising from a tender intimacy, when confidence is unchecked by suspicion, and rendered interesting by sense? (94).
The second section of this chapter focuses on Sermons to Young Women (1766) written by the clergyman James Fordyce and circulated around churches and schools at the time. Like Rousseau, Fordyce reinforces many of the stereotypes regarding women and their frailty, saying that women “are timid and want to be defended” (98). Wollstonecraft critiques Fordyce for his “cold artificial feelings” (98) and his “lover-like phrases of pumped up passion” (99), and continues to disparage Fordyce for comparing woman to angels, stating that his comparison rests purely on their youth and beauty and “consequently, it is their passions, not their virtues, that procure them this homage” (99). She accuses him of being vain and superficial in his understanding and treatment of women. Furthermore, Wollstonecraft argues that Fordyce’s sermons are undifferentiating by seeking to group all women into “one character of yielding softness and gentle compliance” (100), and thus, according to Wollstonecraft, encouraging a woman to act as nothing more than a “house slave” (100).
The third section of this chapter turns to James Gregory’s work A Father’s Legacy to His Daughters (1761). Wollstonecraft first attacks Gregory’s idea regarding “decorum” (102), in which he argues that women should live by a strict set of rules. Wollstonecraft says that if women only follow rules, they have no reason to develop their own rationality and intelligence: “[W]hen the mind has been stored with useful knowledge, and strengthened by being employed, the regulation of the behavior may safely be left to its guidance” (102). If they are given an education, they will not require rules or “decorum,” as they will live like this on their own. Furthermore, Gregory states that women should conceal their true feelings from their husbands. Wollstonecraft objects to “this system of dissimulation” (103) Gregory encourages. Instead, Wollstonecraft encourages women to be truthful and honest and says that “it is far better to be often deceived than never to trust, to be disappointed in love than never to lose; to lose a husband’s fondness than forfeit his esteem” (105).
This chapter’s fourth section examines various works written by other women, including Hester Thrale Piozzi, Germaine de Stael, Madame de Genlis, Hester Chapone, and Catherine Macaulay. With the exception of Hester Chapone’s Letters on the Improvement of the Mind and Catherine Macaulay’s Letters on Education, Wollstonecraft critiques the other woman cited for arguing “in the same track as men” (106) and “[adopting] the sentiments that brutalize them” (106). Primarily, she criticizes these women for stating that the sole purpose of women—as Rousseau, Fordyce, and Gregory similarly argue—is to “gain and keep the heart of man” (106). She cites both Macaulay and Chapone as women who, like her, call for the betterment of women through a rational and more equal education.
The fifth and final section examines Lord Chesterfield’s Letters, a series of published correspondence in which he instructs his son on various topics. Wollstonecraft’s main objection to these Letters is that they preach a set of rules or “precepts” (112) for young people to follow. Wollstonecraft states that if young people merely learn to follow rules, they are only learning to acquire “blind obedience” (112), “instead of preparing young people to encounter the evils of life with dignity and to acquire wisdom and virtue by the exercise of their own faculties” (112). Wollstonecraft also examines and questions the purpose of education: is its purpose the “immortality of the soul” (114), or simply “to secure ease and prosperity on earth” (114)? If the latter, then learning to follow a set of rules is the correct path; however, if it is the former—as Wollstonecraft believes—then young people must learn the difference between good and evil by way of experience and by “[feeling] as men feel before we can judge of their feelings” (117). They must learn for themselves, rather than following a set of rules blindly.
Chapters 4 and 5 continue to expand upon what Wollstonecraft believes to be the perceived and reinforced differences between the sexes, which perpetually put women at a disadvantage to men. Wollstonecraft’s argument in Chapter 4 primarily seeks to address the idea prevalent at her time: that women are born to feel, while men are born to think. Wollstonecraft discredits “sensibility”—or feeling—stating that it is neither a moral nor virtuous attribute, and does not render man (or woman) in the image of God. To be made and act in the image of God is one of the most important Christian values, and so Wollstonecraft argues that by both depicting and enforcing the values of frailty and sensibility onto women, it contradicts the laws of God himself: “I discern not a trace of the image of God in either sensation or matter” (66).
Wollstonecraft also builds upon the arguments of previous chapters about hierarchies and the damage they inflict upon society. She argues that the attributes of frailty and sensibility are perpetuated by women themselves because they are their only source of power within society. Unlike men, who might rise through the ranks of society by education, learning, and work, women can only rise via marriage:
It is not business, extensive plans, or any of the excursive flights of ambition, that engross [women’s] attention; no, their thoughts are not employed in rearing such noble structures. To rise in the world, and have the liberty of running from pleasure to pleasure, they must marry advantageously, and to this object their time is sacrificed, and their persons often legally prostituted. (63)
As a result, women exaggerate the attributes they believe render them pleasing and attractive to men, so that they can rise in station. Ultimately, Wollstonecraft argues against the hierarchies that institute both “blind ignorance” and systems of power that will always place women in a subordinate position to men, forcing them to degrade themselves by reinforcing female stereotypes.
Chapter 5 takes a slightly different format and tone to Wollstonecraft’s other chapters as she works through a number of prominent writers also concerned with female education. This chapter functions, to some degree, like a literature review of her prominent contemporaries, while also taking a highly critical and often disparaging tone towards the majority of writers cited. What this chapter also illustrates is how treatises such as Wollstonecraft’s were not unique for her time; in fact, Wollstonecraft’s work is a very direct response to the numerous other pamphlets and letters being written by men and women alike, most of which functioned as a form of “how to” for female education and behavior. In contrast, Wollstonecraft’s work does not include a strict set of rules and behaviors—as, for example, James Gregory’s A Father’s Legacy to His Daughters and Lord Chesterfield’s Letters do—and instead sets out to expose how such rules are not only degrading for women, but also immoral. In some senses, A Vindication of the Rights of Woman could be read as a “how not to” for female education and behavior.
Furthermore, this fifth chapter provides evidence for the arguments Wollstonecraft makes in previous chapters. With her work, Wollstonecraft attempts to show how the perceived differences between men and women—and the stereotypes of women—are not inherent differences but rather attributes indoctrinated into both sexes from an early age by the educating influence of society. By quoting prominent writers and thinkers of her day whose writings reinforce female stereotypes, Wollstonecraft shows this educating influence in action. All of the writers she cites—if not well known today—were both well-read and well-circulated during the 18th century. As a result, such texts are exactly the type of informal education Wollstonecraft describes in previous chapters as having the power to perpetuate false ideas of women. For example, Wollstonecraft quotes the following passage from Rousseau, which shows very explicitly the type of mentality that Wollstonecraft, and women like her, are up against:
For this reason, the education of the women should be always relative to the men. To please, to be useful to us, to make us love and esteem them, to educate us when young, and take care of us when grown up, to advise, to console us, to render our lives easy and agreeable: these are the duties of women at all times, and what they should be taught in their infancy (84).
It is such ideas and writings—and the influence they have—that Wollstonecraft is hoping to dismantle with A Vindication of the Rights of Woman.
Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.
Including features: